Results

We want to follow the guidance of TRUTH and BAYESIAN to look for the true theory of everything. The plan for this Results section is to list my credences for the various possibilities, along with the works that significantly affected by assignment of credences. The hope is to provide helpful information to readers with a similar interest in theories of everything.

The list I have in mind is long, and what is shown below so far is only a list under construction. It will get longer in time, and I will also rewrite the existing items to make them more accessible. Stay tuned!

Dynamical laws

Gravity

The dynamical laws for gravity may be captured by a theory of quantum gravity, or something else. My current (as of October 8, 2023, based on Section 1.2 of the PhD thesis) credence for the possibilities are:

  1. Geometric-variable path integrals
    Credence: ∼ 50%.
    In General Relativity, gravity is captured by spacetime geometry. Straightforwardly, path integrating over spacetime geometries yield quantum theories of gravity. Examples include versions of simplicial quantum gravity (quantum Regge calculus) and dynamical triangula- tion.I assign the highest credence to this possibility, because it is hardest to argue against. In con- trast to most other theories discussed below, I do not know any way to rule out Lorentzian simplicial quantum gravity (see Chapter 2 of PhD) by comparing with known facts. To know if the extant theories in this category are true, the challenge is to develop techniques to evaluate the path integrals efficiently, draw predictions, gather data, and test against yet unknown facts.
  2. Gauge-variable path integrals
    Credence: ∼ 20%.
    General relativity can be reformulated in terms of frame fields. This leads to alternative gravitational path integrals based on gauge variables. Examples include Ponzano-Regge models, and various spin foam models.For geometric variables, the path integral sum is constrained by inequalities to Lorentzian or Euclidean geometries. For gauge variables, it is far less clear which configurations should be included in the path integral. The many different answers give rise to a large variety of gauge-variable path integrals, of which only a small portion have been studied in detail. The pool is large enough for one to be optimistic that at least one member could be true, but due to limited understanding of the models, there lacks sufficient reason to single out any candidate as particularly promising. Therefore I assign a modest credence.
  3. Causal set path integrals
    Credence: ∼ 3%.
    The causal set approach captures gravity by fundamentally discrete sets, and provides ex- amples for gravitational path integrals based on neither geometric nor gauge variables. Causal set path integrals face some long-standing issues. A causal set does not carry a spacetime dimension, nor a tangent space structure to couple to fermions. Consequently, no extant causal set path integral can be viewed as a viable candidate for the true theory of quantum gravity, and the faint hope has to be set on future inventions.
  1. Holography
    Credence: ∼ 5%.
    As far as our universe goes, AdS/CFT correspondence seems to only supply false theories, because our universe is not AdS.There is the hope that some dS holography theory applicable to our universe will be in- vented in the future. So far so bad, after many years, so my credence is low.
  2. Wheeler-DeWitt equation
    Credence: ∼ 1%.
    Defining a theory of quantum gravity (e.g., Canonical loop quantum gravity; quantum ge- ometrodynamics) by the Wheeler-DeWitt equation Hψ = 0 seems to me to be misguided from the beginning, due to its focus on ψ, instead of empirical predictions. Unlike in un- dergraduate quantum mechanics, where p = |ψ|2, there is no clear way to reach empirical probabilistic predictions p from ψ in the present context.To derive empirical probabilities, one could adopt a functional integral approach (see Chapter 6 of PhD). If one insists on a differential equation approach, one could parameterize the family of mathematical quantities which do yield empirical probabilities, and try to derive an equa- tion of how these quantities change as the parameters vary. This equation may have little to do with the Wheeler-DeWitt equation, which means one should not focus on the Wheeler- DeWitt equation in the first place.
  3. Other known approaches
    Credence: ∼ 5%.
    The other extant approaches I am know of are all quite premature. For instance, functional renormalization group asymptotic safety, developed in the Euclidean setting, is inapplicable in the Lorentzian setting. Perturbative approaches, limited to the perturbative setting, are capable of neither offering a full theory of quantum gravity, nor addressing questions about black hole interior and quantum cosmology, where quantum gravity is actually in need. String theory turns to holography or the distant dream of M-theory to address the challenge for a non-perturbative formulation. The former case does not seem promising, as discussed above, while the latter dream seems to remain distant.Since these are all long-standing issues, unsolved not due to the lack of trying, my credence is low.
  4. Something else
    Credence: ?
    It could be that the true theory is not a quantum theory, or a quantum theory in some brand new approach. I find it difficult to estimate the chance for this possibility, so leave it unspecified.

By the above Bayesian analysis, my current best bet for the correct theory of gravity is a non-perturbatively defined path integral in the metric variable.

In particular, I find most promising the Lorentzian theory developed here:

  • Ding Jia, 2022, “Complex, Lorentzian, and Euclidean simplicial quantum gravity: numerical methods and physical prospects”. [article, arxiv]

Currently, we do not understand the lattice refinement limit of the theory well. Some partial progress are reported in:

  • DJ, 2022, “Light ray fluctuations in simplicial quantum gravity”. [article, arxiv]
  • DJ, 2023, “Light ray fluctuation and lattice refinement of simplicial quantum gravity”. [article, arxiv]

What happens to black hole and cosmological singularities in quantum gravity?

One possibility is that they are avoided trivially:

  • DJ, “Is singularity resolution trivial?”. [arxiv]

The idea is that for some Lorentzian gravitational path integrals, singular configurations are excluded from the sum by definition.

What phenomenological implications does the above mechanism of singularity avoidance have?

  • DJ, “Semiclassical singularity is compatible with quantum singularity avoidance” [ttoe]

The interesting finding is that quantum singularity avoidance sometimes come hand-in-hand with singular semiclassical spacetimes. The result suggests one to consider singular bounce effective spacetimes for phenomenological studies.

Matter

For the dynamical law of matter, the Standard Model of particle physics provides the current best candidate theory. Due to issues such as dark matter, there remains the question what theory captures the full truth of Nature.

My current (as of October 9, 2023, based on Section 1.1 of the PhD thesis) credences are:

  1. Standard Model as it stands, or a straightforward extension
    Credence: > 70%.
    A straightforward extension means an alternative theory with a modified set of matter species or/and a modified Lagrangian (e.g., adding dark matter to the Standard Model), but still within the functional integral framework.My confidence in this possibility is high, because of the empirical success of the Standard Model and the functional integral framework.
  2. Something else
    Credence: < 30%.

How should we understand the Standard Model, intuitively? Is it a theory about fields, particles, something else?

  • Ding Jia, “What should be the ontology for the Standard Model?”. [articlearxiv]
  • Ding Jia, “Path integral and particle ontology”. [arxiv]

In the picture presented in these papers, the Standard Model is a theory about particles and strings, instead of fields. As a feature of the theory, particles and open strings are always coupled. This offers an intuitive and graphical explanation for why the theory obeys gauge symmetry. In addition, some commonly seen arguments against a particle picture for relativistic quantum physics are discussed and refuted in the second paper.

Boundary conditions

Cosmology

In recent years, there has been a surge of interest in studying Lorentzian path integrals for quantum cosmology. Most of these works are not doing it right, since they sum over both Lorentzian and non-Lorentzian gravitational configurations.

  • Ding Jia, “Truly Lorentzian quantum cosmology”. [arXiv]

The above paper shows how to do Lorentzian path integrals right for de Sitter minisuperspace model.

The no-boundary proposals and the tunnelling proposals are the most popular proposals for the boundary conditions of the universe. However, these are not applicable to strictly Lorentzian path integrals, because they impose boundary configurations which are not of the Lorentzian signature.

An old proposal due to Suen and Young in the late 1980s holds that for strictly Lorentzian path integrals, all Lorentzian boundary configurations should be summed over as the boundary condition for the universe. In the above work, the idea was developed to include future boundarys, and to accommodate mixed boundary conditions to make the proposal basis-independent.

Empirical prescriptions

Quantum foundations
  • Ding Jia, “Experience in quantum physics: toward a theory of everything”. [arXiv]
  • Ding Jia, “Modes of experience in a superposed world”. [arXiv]

Additional works by DJ can be found on the google scholar page.